Contents
9 found
Order:
  1. Semiological Conception of Analyticity.Morteza Shahram - manuscript
    In the context of Kripke's puzzle, Paderewski-the-pianist and Paderewski-the-politician are the same object but belong to two different semiotic systems. Their respective tokenings in thought or language are based on two informational contents which are caused by the same object but emitted through two distinct causal pathways. Relativization of the object to the two semiotic systems represent elements of a set of ___coreferential homonyms___. Every F is an F = Everything X that is conspicuously or demonstratively an F is something (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Kripkenstein’s Monster: An Origin Story.Joanna Lawson - forthcoming - Erkenntnis:1-22.
    Kripke thought that the meaning paradox articulated in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language arises due to a logical tension. This diagnosis, however, doesn’t account for the enduring controversy surrounding the paradox. I argue that the meaning paradox stems instead from a tension inherent in two conflicting philo- sophical methodologies: theoretical internalism and theoretical externalism. Inter- nalism, as a philosophical methodology, takes for granted the contents of our minds, whereas externalism takes for granted empirical data and shared notions of common (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Variabilism in light of Naming and Necessity.Anders J. Schoubye & Brian Rabern - forthcoming - In Corine Besson, Anandi Hattiangadi, Romina Padro & Antonella Mallozzi, 50 Years of Naming and Necessity.
    We assess the compatibility of Variabilism -- the view that bare singular uses of proper names are best modeled as individual variables -- with the arguments and insights of Kripke's _Naming and Necessity_. After clarifying the view and tracing its historical development, we present a presuppositional variant that treats names as assignment-dependent variables constrained by naming presuppositions, akin to pronouns. We argue that this account accommodates Kripke's three central arguments against Descriptivism (semantic, epistemic, and modal), as well as his circularity (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Alethic Modalities.Nathan Salmón - 2025 - Philosophical Studies 182 (1):287-304.
    It is widely held that metaphysical modality is the broadest non-epistemic, alethic modality, and that /a posteriori/ modal essentialist truths, like that gold has atomic number 79, enjoy the necessity of the broadest alethic modality. One prominent argument for these conclusions--given by Cian Dorr, John Hawthorne, and Juhani Yli-Vakkuri--rests upon an extremely dubious premise: that certain pairs of properties—e.g., being gold and being made of atoms containing 79 protons—are one and the very same property. The two properties are seen to (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Answering Kripke's skeptic : dispositions without 'dispositionalism'.Henry Jackman - 2024 - In Claudine Verheggen, Kripke's Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language at 40. New York,:
    In his Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Saul Kripke famously raised two sorts of problems for responses to the meaning skeptic that appealed to how we were disposed to use our words in the past. The first related to the fact that our “dispositions extend to only finitely many cases” while the second related to the fact that most of us have “dispositions to make mistakes.” The second of these problems has produced an enormous, and still growing, literature on (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Kripke against Kripkenstein.Jaakko Reinikainen - 2022 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 11 (4):241-248.
    What was Saul Kripke’s personal stance on the sceptical challenge that he famously attributed to Ludwig Wittgenstein? It will be argued that despite his statements to the contrary, we can, in fact, outline at least a rough sketch of Kripke’s own views on the challenge and its aftermath on the basis of the remarks he left in the text. In summary, Kripke (a) rejected the sceptical solution to the challenge and (b) leaned towards a non-sceptical primitivist solution. If this is (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. That’s the Guy Who Might Have Lost.Tristan Grøtvedt Haze - 2020 - Analytic Philosophy 62 (4):418-426.
    In an influential passage of Naming and Necessity Kripke argues, with the help of a fictional dialogue, that de re metaphysical modal distinctions have intuitive content. In this note I clarify the workings of the argument, and what it does and does not support. I conclude that Kripke’s argument does not, despite possible appearances, support the view that metaphysical modal distinctions are made in common sense discourse. The argument does however support the view that if metaphysical modal distinctions make sense (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Kripkenstein and Aborigines: The True Order of Language and Rule-Following Paradox.A. Nekhaev - 2013 - Tomsk State University Journal of Philosophy, Sociology and Political Science 7 (2):143-155.
    This article is devoted to thirtieth anniversary of the first publication in 1982 Saul Kripke's book "Wittgenstein on rules and private language". Radical skeptical interpretation of the work 'late' Ludwig Wittgenstein proposed by Saul Kripke in this book is considered one of the most famous "puzzle" of modern philosophy of language, which has become a source of much debate and discussion on the nature of the linguistic sign and its meaning. This article examines some of the consequences of a radical (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Chapter 36. Modality.Sanford Shieh - 2013 - In Michael Beaney, The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 1043-1081.
    This chapter examines modality in the history of analytic philosophy. There were, in this history, two principal types of reductionism or eliminativism about modality, and two corresponding phases in the rejection of anti-modal stances. First, the founders of analytic philosophy, Frege, Moore, and Russell, took necessity and possibility to be reducible to more fundamental logical notions, where logic for these thinkers consists of truths about a mind- and language-independent reality extending beyond the empirical world. Against this reductionism, C. I. Lewis (...)
    Remove from this list   Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
OSZAR »